They are the Future of Humanity

Sunday, July 7, 2013

Mapping Truth: Godel and Incompleteness Part I

Yet one can’t do any mathematics at all, not even basic arithmetic, without referring implicitly to the infinite.
(Rebecca Goldstein, Incompleteness: 186)


In 1931 a young logician, Kurt Godel, transformed the study of logic, especially mathematical logic, and epistemology, by proving that all formal systems of human thought are inherently incomplete.  His groundbreaking, paradigm-busting, work was titled: On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems. It yielded two famous theorems, called Godel’s incompleteness theorems.
The Principia Mathematica was a work of mathematical logic by Bertrand Russell and Alfred North Whitehead that attempted to set forth a complete and consistent formal, logical foundation and the essential principles of mathematics.  They claimed that they had done so, but upon closer examination it was found that to achieve consistency Russell and Whitehead had introduced some ad hoc principles.  A formal system, in mathematics at least, is one that is divested of all appeals to intuition.  It is a closed, axiomatic system of reasoning with primitive givens, stipulated rules of inference and proved theorems.  Because it is closed, it is finite.  There can be nothing ad hoc about it.
An axiomatic system is consistent when employing the rules of the system generates no contradictions, and consistency itself is one of the propositions of the system.  Thus, every axiom, or true statement, must be derived from the basic principles and rules of the system.  Too, no statement can be both true and false at the same time.  It is a real left-brainer construct.  Godel discovered and proved that neither the truth nor the falsity of some propositions of any formal system of thought can be proved.  That is, a proposition may be true, contextually, but it can’t be proved to be true.  It can only be proved to be unprovable.  Thus, to prove the truth of these formally undecidable propositions requires another, richer kind of thought-structure.  Thus the formal system is incomplete.  
Mind can never embrace the totality, because as Hamlet told Horatio: “There are more things in heaven and earth, Horatio, Than are dreamt of in your philosophy.” (Hamlet 1:5)  If any contradiction arises, or if a true proposition or statement cannot be proven using only the rules of the system, then the system is inconsistent (a bad thing for formalists) and incomplete (that’s OK, so long as a higher system of thought can complete it).  How to get out of this?  Think—go right-brained.  The problem comes with self-referential statements.  These operate at the limits of formal systems, defining their boundaries of truth, sort of like the complexity or chaos sciences.     
For example take the famous liar’s paradox: This statement is untrue.  Taken by itself, with no reference to anything else, if it is true, then it is a contradiction, because it says that it is untrue.  If it is untrue, then it is also a contradiction because that would mean that it is true.  Consistency is broken, and the only way out is to introduce something new into the system of thought, or to refer outside to the system to a context.  Godel proved that no axiomatic system can be sufficiently rich to formally capture even arithmetic. All formal systems are incomplete, deriving their consistency from appealing to a richer formal system. 
He proved this for all formal systems by showing how the truth or falsity of some propositions is not formally decidable using the rules of the system.  That is, the question, can a particular proposition be proved within the system sometimes yields the answer that it can’t be proved.  How? 
A particular proposition (A) is unprovable in the system if the negation of A is another proposition: A is provable in the system.  But if A were provable then its negation—which says that A is provable—would be true.  But if the negation of a proposition is true, then the proposition itself is false.  So if A is provable then it is false.  But if A is provable, then it is also true.  So, assuming the consistency of the system, if A is provable then it is both true and false—a contradiction—which means that A is not provable.  But that is exactly what A said in the first place: that it is not provable.  So A is true.  Therefore, A is both unprovable and true and this is expressible within the system.  The final conclusion is that the formal system is either inconsistent or incomplete, which are the two-sides of one coin.  The proof rests on the method of assigning a number to statements so that a blending of voices—arithmetical and metaarithmetical—is accomplished such that arithmetical statements are also making metaarithmetical statements: i.e. statements about arithmetic made in numbers, each statement assigned a number.  This is possible because language and number are both symbol systems--i.e. numbers can be assigned letters and letters numbers, as in numerology.
In using the same language of arithmetic, i.e. the map, to express both meanings and metameanings, two different sorts of descriptions will be collapsed into one another.  It is introducing an element of the organization of events on the level of events itself, as if the thoughts organizing your physical behavior were themselves part of your physical behavior.  In arithmetic, arithmetical descriptions setting forth relationships between numbers are, of course, expressible within the formal system e.g. 2+2=4.  But if, as Godel did, you assign a number to a metastatement about arithmetic (e.g. the rule that the sum of two integers is another integer could be given the number 5) then metadescriptions about the logical relationships holding between numbers (i.e. the syntax of the language) can be described within the formal system itself.  Metastatements are purely syntactic, i.e. rules about rules.  They can not be proved to be true or false using the rules of the system.  They are simply unproveable.  That is, it is not about the truth or falsity of any statement, but about its proveability to be one or the other.  Rebecca Goldstein sums up the results: “Godel’s first incompleteness theorem tells us that any consistent formal system adequate for the expression of arithmetic must leave out much of mathematical reality, and his second theorem tells us that no such formal system can even prove itself to be self-consistent.” (Incompleteness: 192)
That is, the syntactic features of formal mathematical systems (e.g. the rules of combining numbers in arithmetic) can’t capture all the truths about the system, including the truth of its own consistency.  Consistency, which defines the system, transcends the grasp of the system itself: consistency is not completeness.  Completeness is something else.  There is something within all formal system that is not “of itself’ but is the representation of a higher entity to the system: paradoxically, what makes the system a system by being something else.    This "something else" completes the system, or, at least, is the means of its completeness.  Consistency is not within any system, but only as part of a richer system, which is also only fully consistent within yet another, higher system. 
In any universe of discourse, whether language or number, this kind of confusion of realms that arises with self-referencing—where the metasyntactic and the syntactic statements collapse into one another, so that the logical relations that hold between units of meaning (e.g. numbers and their relations) in the formal system themselves become relations expressible in the language of the system—is the mechanism of encoding complexity, for it allows an entity of a higher level of reality to exist in some form in a lower level of reality.  Potentially, infinite meanings can then be expressed in finite language if they become self-referential in a higher sense.  OK, so what?  
The implications are terrific. But that is for next post.

No comments:

Post a Comment